Information theory, as its name suggests, is the study of informati...
Many of the authors from this paper work at the Santa Fe institute....
Here is a great background article on this topic, with quotes from ...
Nature of life is process-driven. Recall Alfred North Whitehead's p...
"What Is Life? The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell" by the Nobel...
"In an ideal case, visitors to an exoplanet would have a procedure ...
Even though the existence of DNA had been known since 1869, its rol...
This paper similarly takes a Schrödinger-esque leap in their theore...
The key question of this paper: "The question we seek to address...
These points outline the main theories of individuality exposited i...
This is the famous Entropy formula from Claude Shannon's work on in...
Vol.:(0123456789)
1 3
Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
https://doi.org/10.1007/s12064-020-00313-7
ORIGINAL ARTICLE
The information theory ofindividuality
DavidKrakauer
1
· NilsBertschinger
3
· EckehardOlbrich
2
· JessicaC.Flack
1
· NihatAy
1,2
Received: 6 January 2020 / Accepted: 5 March 2020 / Published online: 24 March 2020
© The Author(s) 2020
Abstract
Despite the near universal assumption of individuality in biology, there is little agreement about what individuals are and
few rigorous quantitative methods for their identification. Here, we propose that individuals are aggregates that preserve a
measure of temporal integrity, i.e., “propagate” information from their past into their futures. We formalize this idea using
information theory and graphical models. This mathematical formulation yields three principled and distinct forms of
individuality—an organismal, a colonial, and a driven form—each of which varies in the degree of environmental depend-
ence and inherited information. This approach can be thought of as a Gestalt approach to evolution where selection makes
figure-ground (agent–environment) distinctions using suitable information-theoretic lenses. A benefit of the approach is that
it expands the scope of allowable individuals to include adaptive aggregations in systems that are multi-scale, highly dis-
tributed, and do not necessarily have physical boundaries such as cell walls or clonal somatic tissue. Such individuals might
be visible to selection but hard to detect by observers without suitable measurement principles. The information theory of
individuality allows for the identification of individuals at all levels of organization from molecular to cultural and provides
a basis for testing assumptions about the natural scales of a system and argues for the importance of uncertainty reduction
through coarse-graining in adaptive systems.
Keywords Shannon information· Mutual information· Information decomposition· Shared information· Synergy·
Adaptation· Evolution· Control· Gestalt
The architecture ofindividuality
From the perspective of physics and chemistry, biological
life is surprising. There is no physical or chemical theory
from which we can predict biology, and yet if we break
down any biological system into its elementary constituents,
there is no chemistry or physics remaining unaccounted for
(Gell-Mann 1995). The fact that physics and chemistry are
universal—ongoing in stars, solar systems, and galaxies—
whereas to the best of our knowledge biology is exclusively
a property of earth, supports the view that life is emergent.
This stands in contrast to the universality of chemical phe-
nomena which can be predicted from quantum mechanical
considerations in fundamental physics even when this proves
to be computationally cumbersome or intractable (Defranc-
eschi and Le Bris 2000). The asymmetry in what can be
gleaned from working down toward ever more elementary
constituents versus working up through levels of aggrega-
tion is captured by the terms reductionism and emergence
(Anderson 1972; Laughlin and Pines 2000). It is often
difficult to predict physical properties of aggregates from
knowledge of constituents, and this extends to questions
of behavior where it is rarely clear how far “down” to go
(Anderson 1972; Krakauer and Flack 2010a; Flack 2017b).
There are assumed to be dominant microscopic scales for
a given set of aggregate properties yet our understanding
of what constitutes a fundamental unit (Gilbert etal. 2012;
Daniels etal. 2016) and whether these units count as indi-
viduals, have implications for many areas of science, from
taxonomy and cladistics through to physiology, behavior,
and ecology (Clarke 2011; Wilson and Barker 2013).
It is almost inconceivable for us to imagine a biological
science without a concept of units or individuality. After
all, how could we speak about metabolism, behavior or
* David Krakauer
krakauer@santafe.edu
1
Santa Fe Institute, SantaFe, USA
2
Max Planck Institute forMathematics intheSciences,
Leipzig, Germany
3
Frankfurt Institute forAdvanced Studies, FrankfurtamMain,
Germany
210 Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
the genome without first establishing a unit or container
of observation and measurement? Even Schrödinger in his
prescient book, What is Life? (Schrodinger 2012), sought to
explore the persistence of biological phenotypes of organ-
isms—or even features of ecosystems—through the lens
of elementary and universal physical underpinnings, made
strong prior assumptions about the reality of individual
organisms:
“What degree of permanence do we encounter in heredi-
tary properties and what must we therefore attribute to the
material structures which carry them? The answer to this can
really be given without any special investigation. The mere
fact that we speak of hereditary properties indicates that we
recognize the permanence to be of the almost absolute. For
we must not forget that what is passed on by the parent to
the child is not just this or that peculiarity...Such features we
may conveniently select for studying the laws of heredity.
But actually it is the whole (four- dimensional) pattern of
the phenotype, all the visible and manifest nature of the indi-
vidual, which is reproduced without appreciable change for
generations, permanent within centuries—though not within
tens of thousands of years—and borne at each transmission
by the material in a structure of the nuclei of the two cells
which unite to form the fertilized egg cell. That is a marvel.
Schrödinger did not set out to derive the individual from
fundamental physics but to reconcile existing and rather tra-
ditional conceptions of individuality (essentially the indi-
vidual as synonymous with the observable organism) with
the new physics of quantum mechanics.
In this respect, Schrödinger was adopting a typically
reductionist perspective, explaining features of biological
science through first principles of physics (Weinberg 1995).
In Schrödingers case, the physical feature of greatest impor-
tance to biology was the long-lived covalent bond. But for
many reasons this line of approach has failed to deliver
the deep and unifying insights based on physics (Ander-
son 1972), from which powerful biological ideas—such as
adaptation or individuality—might be derived (Dupré 2009;
Keller 2009).
The question we seek to address is more limited. How
do we identify individuals without relying on features like
cell membranes that may be solutions to challenges faced by
particular systems for maintaining integrity rather than foun-
dational properties? We want to allow for the possibility that
microbes and loosely bound ecological assemblages such as
microbial mats and cultural and technological systems, when
viewed with a mathematical lens, qualify as individuals even
though their boundaries are more fluid than the organisms
we typically allow. It may also be the case that entities cur-
rently considered individuals are indeed individuals but
not in the way we think—organisms are more complicated
than typical individuality definitions acknowledge. Humans
for example contain approximately as many self-cells as
symbiotic microbes (Andreu-Moreno and Sanjuán 2018),
yet until recently with the advent of the concept of “holobi-
ont” (Gilbert etal. 2012), the microbe portion of the human
cellular ecosystem was not typically considered part of the
human individual.
In an ideal case, visitors to an exoplanet would have a
procedure for identifying or “perceiving” individuals based
on a quantitative survey with minimal prior knowledge of
the type of life form that they expect to encounter. In the next
sections of the paper, we briefly review a few key standard
assumptions about individuality in biology and challenges
to formalizing the concept. We then discuss a way forward
and develop an information-theoretic formalism.
Standard assumptions andchallenges
Here, we briefly review some of the criteria currently used
to identify individuals. For a synoptic treatment of individu-
ality definitions see (Clarke 2011; Gilbert etal. 2012). A
standard assumption is that replication presupposes indi-
viduality (Wilson and Barker 2013). Under this assumption,
replicators typically include organisms that have developed
from a fertilized egg, with individuality residing at the phe-
notypic level (see Dawkins 1983), and asexual microbes or
clonal organisms for which individuality is defined based
on shared genetic ancestry (Hughes 1990). The replicator
assumption has served as the starting point for theorizing
about what an individual is in a broad class of studies and
out of this work has come three additional widely accepted
properties of biological individuals: (1) they can increase in
relative frequency by exploiting a source of metabolic free
energy, (2) they respond adaptively to their environments,
and (3) they are characterized by tightly coordinated rela-
tionships (chemical, physiological, computational) among
their parts. The association of these properties with individu-
ality has raised debate about whether individuality applies
only to “single” organisms, as the replicator assumption
suggestions, or also to cells and aggregates like societies
(Gilbert etal. 2012).
Beyond replicators as proxies for an individuals, almost
all definitions of individuality assume a set members (indi-
vidual) and a set complement (environment). These are artic-
ulated in different ways including: (1) as an immunological
concept pertaining to the idea of self and non-self (Pradeu
2012), (2) as a temporal aggregate encoding a common past
separable or independent from the past of other aggregates
(ontogenetic or phylogenetic) (Rieppel 2013) (3) as a spa-
tially bounded collection of metabolic reactions insulated by
a membrane from reactions in the environment (Rasmussen
etal. 2004), and more abstractly, (4) as a unit of selection
and evolutionary change (Buss 1987; Hughes 1990; Szath-
máry and Smith 1997; Callcott and Sterelny 2011).
211Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
To reveal limitations of the above definitions and other
hidden assumptions, a useful exercise is to consider aggre-
gates and processes that do not typically get classified as
individuals (Santelices 1999).
Work on social insects and on a number of plant, fun-
gal and prokaryotic species demonstrates the possibility
of individuality simultaneously at multiple organizational
levels—physically distinct ants form aggregations called
colonies and these colonies may be divided into spatially
noncontiguous subsets (Gow etal. 2008; Esser etal. 2001).
Furthermore, in many ant species the majority of worker
ants do not replicate and the colony as whole does not repli-
cate, but contiguity between past and future is nonetheless a
feature of the system. And, importantly, it is the combination
of reproduction by a minority of colony members coupled
to the industry of the majority that allows the colony as a
whole to adapt in response to changes in the environment.
Taken together, these two observations suggest it is possible
to have individuality without replication and some forms of
individuality benefit when replication is partial.
Viruses occupy a figurative twilight zone in biology.
Declared by some non-living, and treated by most as a
rather pathetic minimal limit of life, viruses constitute obli-
gate translational parasites, incapable of completing their
life cycles without first appropriating the protein synthesis
machinery of a host cell. The viral capsid contains a largely
inert genome responsible for encoding only a small fraction
of the proteins required for synthesizing a new virus genome
and the capsid required for egressing from the infected cell.
The virus exists only within the larger dynamical, regulatory
network of the cell. Hence, the virus—understood as the
active parasitic agent—is comprised largely of host encoded
factors. And yet it can replicate, adapt, and has a persistent
identity that distinguishes it from its “host” environment—
despite the fact it relies on its “host” environment for repli-
cating. And, recent work suggests that viruses like microbes
form collective units that facilitate infection (Andreu-
Moreno and Sanjuán 2018). These observations suggest that
viruses in aggregate are individuals but not in the conven-
tional sense. Rather they are what Krakauer (Krakauer and
Zanotto 2006) has called “chimerical individuals.
A way forward
The above examples are fascinating but without a rigorous
definition of both the environment and the agent it is difficult
to speak consistently of individuals. This is analogous to
figure-ground separation in gestalt psychology or computer
vision. The background of an image carries as much if not
more information than the object, and the challenge is to
separate the two rather than assume that they are already
distinct and independent.
One possibility is that ant colonies and viruses [or
humans, for that matter, composed of 37 trillion microbes
and 30 trillion “human” cells (Andreu-Moreno and Sanjuán
2018; Gilbert etal. 2012)] are only nominally individual—
a categorization resulting from human perceptual bias for
certain kinds of aggregation. But if they are real in a deeper
physical sense then how might we determine this? We
propose:
Individuality can be continuous, with the possible sur-
prising result that some processes possess greater indi-
viduality than others.
Individuality can emerge at any level of organization.
This requires we dispense with privileging a single level
or object—for example, replicating cells or organisms—
and then defining individuality based on features of these
objects, such as sequestered germ cells, vertical transmis-
sion of genetic material, a common pool of metabolic
free energy, or coordinated immune responses. Although
these features may indeed be effective proxies when we
have significant prior knowledge of a system, our goal
should be to find fundamental, rather that derivative,
properties of individuality. Defining individuality around
derived properties risks precluding the possibility of indi-
viduality in at super-organismal levels and in distributed
systems.
Individuality can be nested. Given that life is hierarchi-
cally organized into trophic and functional levels, we
allow the possibility of multiple, parallel levels of indi-
viduality. We take this position to be related to the recent
suggestion of (Rieppel 2013) where he argues for indi-
viduals based on hierarchical complexes of homeostatic
properties and (Flack 2017a) who has proposed biologi-
cal systems are information hierarchies resulting from the
collective effects of components estimating, in evolution-
ary or ecological time, regularities in their environments
by coarse-graining or compressing time series data and
using these perceived regularities to tune strategies. As
coarse-grained (slow) variables become for components
better predictors than microscopic behavior (which fluc-
tuates), and component estimates of these variables con-
verge, new levels of organization consolidate.
Allowing individuality to be continuous rather than binary,
nested, and possible at any level, opens the door for more
quantitative takes on familiar open questions in evolu-
tionary theory including the relation between the units of
selection and temporal and spatial correlation and whether
individuality at one scale impacts coherence and autonomy
and “lower” and “higher” scales. These revealed time and
space scales and their interdependencies should provide
clues about the mechanisms driving their consolidation and
212 Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
through this consolidation the emergence of individuals
(Flack 2017a, b).
Given our proposition that individuals are aggregates
that “propagate” information from the past to the future and
have temporal integrity, and that individuality is a matter of
degree, can be nested, distributed and possible at any level,
how can we formalize individuality?
Formalizing individuality
We will take as our starting point measurements from a
stochastic process. This could be a vector of chemical con-
centrations over time, the abundance of various cell types,
or probabilities of observing coherent behaviors. We use
coarse-grained or quantized information-theoretic filters the
quantize the measurements. Some of these filters will reveal
a coordinated pattern of behavior, whereas others will filter
out all signal and detect nothing. Thus, signal amplitude
given an appropriate filter becomes a means of discovering
different forms of individuality. This is somewhat analo-
gous to observing patterns in infrared that would be invis-
ible using the wavelengths of visible light—individuality is
revealed through characteristic patterns of information flow.
The basis for this approach to aggregation comes from
information theory, and throughout this paper we assume
that individuals are best thought of in terms of dynamical
processes and not as stationary objects that leave informa-
tion-theoretic traces. In this respect, our approach might rea-
sonably be framed through the lens of “process philosophy”
(Rescher 2007) which makes the elucidation of the dynami-
cal and coupled properties of natural phenomena the primary
explanatory challenge. From the perspective of “process
philosophy,” the tendency of starting with objects and then
listing their properties—“substance metaphysics”—places
the cart before the horse.
The origin ofinformation
Our proposal that individuals are aggregates that propagate
information from the past to the future and have temporal
integrity can be viewed as a pragmatic operational definition
that captures the idea there is something persistent about
individuals. However, our motivation for defining individu-
ality this way is actually much deeper. It lies in the informa-
tion-theoretic interpretation of entropy, its connection to the
physical theory of thermodynamics, and formal definition of
work introduced by Clausius in the 1860s [see (Müller 2007)
for an introduction to this history].
Briefly, work (displacement of a physical system) is
produced by transferring thermal energy from one body to
another (heat). Entropy captures, or measures, the loss in
temperature over the range of motion of the working body. In
other words, entropy measures the energy lost from the total
available energy available for performing work. The insights
of Clausius were formalized and placed in a mathematical
framework by Gibbs in 1876.
In 1877, Boltzmann provided in his kinetic theory of gas-
ses an alternative interpretation of entropy. For Boltzmann
entropy is a measure of the potential disorder in a system.
This definition shifts the emphasis from energy dissipated
through work to the number of unobservable configurations
(microstates) of a system, e.g., particle velocities consistent
with an observable measurement (macrostate), e.g., temper-
ature. The thermodynamic and Boltzmann definitions are
closely related as Boltzmann entropy increases following the
loss of energy available for work attendant upon the colli-
sion of particles in motion during heat flow. There are many
different microscopic configurations of individual particles
compatible with the same macroscopic measurement, and
only a few of which are useful.
In 1948, encouraged by John von Neumann, Claude Shan-
non used the thermodynamical term entropy to capture the
information capacity of a communication channel. A string
of a given length (macrostate) is compatible with a large
number of different sequences of symbols (microstates). A
target word will be disordered during transmission in pro-
portion to the noise in a channel. If there were no noise,
each and every microstate could be resolved and the entropy
would define an upper limit on the number of signals that
could be transmitted. The study of the maximum number
of states that can be transmitted from one point to another
across a channel, in the face of noise and when efficiently
encoded, is called information theory.
Shannon did not describe entropy in terms of heat flow
and work but in terms of information shared through a chan-
nel transmitted from a signaler to a receiver. The power of
information theory derives in part from the incredible gen-
erality of Shannons scheme. The signaler can be a phone in
Madison and the receiver a phone in Madrid, or the signaler
can be a parent and the receiver its offspring. For phones, the
channel is a fiber-optic cable and the signal pulses of light.
For organisms the channel is the germ line and the signal the
sequence of DNA or RNA polynucleotides in the genome.
Increasing entropy for a phone-call corresponds to the loss
or disruption of light-pulses, whereas increasing entropy
during inheritance corresponds to mutation or developmen-
tal noise. The same scheme can be applied to development,
in which case the signaler is an organism in the past and the
receiver the same organism in the future. One way in which
we might identify individuals is to check to see whether we
are dealing with the same aggregation at time t and
t + 1
.
If the information transmitted forward in time is close to
maximal, we take that as evidence for individuality.
In its simplest form, Shannon made use of the following
formal measures when defining information. The entropy
213Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
H of a random variable S measures the uncertainty or
information of the states that it can adopt:
where
s
i
are the possible values of the state and
P(s
i
)
the
probabilities of these states. For a coin there would be two
possible values for S, heads and tails, and the values of these
states for a fair coin would be the probability 0.5, yielding
a metric entropy value of 1. Deviation from a fair coin cor-
responds to a reduction in information, as in the limit of
bias where only one side of the coin is favored, the outcome
is known in advance and any toss of the coin is perfectly
predictable. This produces an entropy value of 0. Hence,
information is minimized when predictability is maximized.
To capture the communication value of information
Shannon introduced a signaler–receiver structure, which
is now typically described using two random variables S
and R. The maximum information transmitted between
signaler and receiver is given by the Mutual Information
(I). The I can be written in several different forms. One
intuitive expression is:
where H(S) and H(R) are the entropies of the signals, and
H(S; R) the joint entropy of the two variables,
The joint entropy is at a maximum when there is no rela-
tionship between the S and R variables. The I is therefore
high when the information in S and R are high and they
are strongly coupled in their values (H(S; R) is low). The
I measures the information shared between S and R over a
communication channel, because the only source of structure
in R is assumed to come from S.
Another conventional way of writing I is,
where H(S|R) is the conditional entropy of R or the amount
of information in R that is not in S. Hence, if all the infor-
mation in R comes from S then H(R|S) will be zero, and
I(S;R)=H(R)
. If one of the random variables, for exam-
ple the sender S consists of two parts
S ={S
1
, S
2
}
, we can
decompose the mutual information using the chain rule
(Cover and Thomas 1991)
with the second term being the conditional mutual
information
H
(S)=−
i
P(s
i
) log
2
P(s
i
)
I(S;R)=H(S)+H(R)−H(S, R)
H
(S;R)=−
i
j
P(s
i
, r
j
) log
2
P(s
i
, r
j
)
I(S
1
, S
2
; R)=I(S
1
; R)+I(S
2
; R|S
1
)
These measures provide the necessary statistics for an infor-
mational theory of the individual.
When we model the interaction between a system and
its environment we have to consider a more complicated
situation which involves two channels. To be more precise,
let
S
and
E
be the state set of the system and the environ-
ment. For simplicity, we assume that
S
and
E
are finite. The
dynamics of the system is influenced by its own state, but it
can also be influenced by the state of the environment. This
can be modeled in terms of a channel
𝜑 E × S
S
, where
𝜑(e, s;s
)
denotes the probability of the next system state
s
given that the current system state is s and the environment
is in state e. In particular, we assume that
𝜑(e, s;s
)
0
for
all
e, s, s
, and
s
𝜑(
e
,
s
;
s
)=1
for all e, s. We can model
the dynamics of the environment in the same way, using a
Markov kernel
𝜓 S × E
E
, where
𝜓 (s, e;e
)
denotes the
probability for the next state
e
of the environment given the
current states e and s of the environment and the system,
respectively. The kernels
𝜑
and
𝜓
model the mechanisms
that constitute the system–environment interaction. If we
start this interaction process by selecting a states s and e
according to some probability distribution
𝜇
, we obtain a
process
(S
k
, E
k
)
,
k = 1, 2,
, in
S × E
that satisfies
Clearly, we can recover the mechanisms from the distribu-
tion of the process
(S
k
, E
k
)
,
k = 1, ,
We apply information-theoretic quantities, such as the
mutual information, to variables of the process
(S
k
, E
k
)
,
thereby quantifying information flows between the sys-
tem and the environment. The causal structure of the pro-
cess, as shown in Fig.1, implies a number of conditional
I(S
2
; R|S
1
) ∶= H(R|S
1
)−H(R|S
1
, S
2
).
(S
1
= s
1
, E
1
= e
1
, S
2
= s
2
, E
2
= e
2
, , S
n
= s
n
, E
n
= e
n
)
= 𝜇(s
1
, e
1
) 𝜑(e
1
, s
1
;s
2
)𝜓 (s
1
, e
1
;e
2
)…
𝜑(e
n1
, s
n1
;s
n
)𝜓 (s
n1
, e
n1
;e
n
), n = 1, 2, .
(S
1
= s, E
1
= e)=𝜇(s, e),
(S
k
= s
| E
k1
= e, S
k1
= s)=𝜑(e, s;s
),
(E
k
= e
| S
k1
= s, E
k1
= e)=𝜓 (s, e;e
).
Fig. 1 The causal diagram of the system–environment interaction
214 Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
independence statements. For instance
E
n+1
is conditionally
independent of
S
n
, E
n
given
S
n1
, E
n1
.
The informational individual
In the previous section, we set down the information-the-
oretic foundations for our formalism. Here, we discuss the
additional mathematical properties required of the formalism
if it is to capture the concept of individuality we developed
in “A way forward” section.
We remind the reader our starting point is the assumption
that biological individuality can usefully be understood as
an “informational individual.” We further remind the reader
this is not to be confused with Dawkins replicator, as we
want to allow the possibility that replication is not a fun-
damental feature of individuality and be able to ask what
role individuality plays in facilitating replication. What is
fundamental in our view is the idea that information can be
propagated forward through time, meaning that uncertainty
is reduced over time. In this way, and returning to our open-
ing remarks in “A way forward” section, we suggest indi-
viduality is a natural extension of the ideas of Boltzmann
and Von Neumann, and as such has foundations in statistical
mechanics and thermodynamics, which consider the condi-
tions required for a persistently ordered states.
Defining properties and implications of the formalism
1 The system environment decomposition Consider a
dynamical set of quantifiable measurements that we
coarse grain into components of a system and compo-
nents of an environment. We seek a way of establish-
ing whether this partition is justifiable, and whether the
individuality concept is relevant. We wish to allow for
a hierarchy of such partitions in order to capture bio-
logical examples such as organelles within cells, and
cells within bodies within populations, where in each
case the target entity and the environment assume a
different identity. We retain those partitions that meet
our information-theoretic inclusion criteria and then
can ask which among the natural, intuitive categories
of biology—e.g., cells, organelles, organisms, popula-
tions, etc., are recovered.
2 Informational individuals In the pursuit of generality, we
consider a discrete, stochastic process where the state of
the system in the future is determined by some subset of
states in the present. If we arbitrarily divide these states
into system and environment, we should like to be able
to determine how the current system state
S
n
and the cur-
rent state of the environment
E
n
together are sufficient
to determine the next system state
S
n+1
. Formally, the
predictability of the next state of the system is quantified
via the mutual information:
This expression seeks to capture how much information
at time
n + 1
S
n+1
comes from the system itself at a previ-
ous time step (or generation)
S
n
—the individual—versus
from the environment at a previous time
E
n
. This mutual
information can now be decomposed in two ways
Each decomposition can be interpreted as different
allocation for distributing the observed past regularities
between the system and environment. Each of these will
allow us to define different forms of individuality.
a Endogenous determination Consider
I(
S
n+1
;
S
n
)+
I
(
S
n+1
;
E
n
|
S
n
)
:
Here, we measure the influence of the system state
onto itself (at the next generation or time step). For
a preferred interval of time, all observed dependen-
cies between successive system states are attributed
to the system.
The quantity
I(S
n+1
;S
n
)
has been called autonomy
in Krakauer and Zanotto (2006) and will be denoted
as
A
in the following. It should be high when the
system is largely control of its environment.
The influence of the environment, as measured by
I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)
, can be interpreted as new information
for the system flowing from the environment into
the system. When this information flow vanishes
completely, a system can be said to be information-
ally closed. So this quantity measures the degree to
which the system is controlled by the environment
nC. Note that closure does not require causal inde-
pendence, it only states that all influences from the
environment are predictable by the system.
b Environmentally driven An alternative to endog-
enous determination is structure imposed largely
through environmental gradients driving the system.
In other words, the history of the system is not as
consequential as the history of the environment that
impose strong boundary conditions on the system.
Consider
I(
S
n+1
;
E
n
)+
I
(
S
n+1
;
S
n
|
E
n
)
:
Here, the observed influences are attributed
to the environment (as far as possible accord-
ing to
I(S
n+1
;E
n
)
). Only the remaining influence
I(
S
n+1
;
S
n
|
E
n
)
is due to the system. This can be inter-
preted as an alternative concept of system autonomy
(Bertschinger etal. 2008) and will be denoted as A
in the following. It is valid under the assumption that
all dependencies between the states of the system
I(S
n
, E
n
; S
n+1
)=H(S
n+1
)−H(S
n+1
|S
n
, E
n
).
I(S
n
, E
n
;S
n+1
)=I(S
n+1
;S
n
)+I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)
= I(S
n+1
;E
n
)+I(S
n+1
;S
n
|
E
n
)
215Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
and the environment are attributed to the environ-
ment.
These properties allow us to identify three quantities,
each corresponding to a type of individuality:
To rigorously formalize these different types of indi-
viduality, however, we need to consider them on a more
fine-grained scale.
Fine‑grained decomposition
Using the chain rule for mutual information, we encounter
an ambiguity in attributing influence to the environment or
to the system. The partial information decomposition (Wil-
liams and Beer 2010; Bertschinger etal. 2013). allows us
to resolve this ambiguity by introducing notions of unique,
shared and complementary information.
1
The mutual information between the future state of the
system at time
n + 1
and the joint state of system and envi-
ronment at time n is decomposed into four terms:
Those four terms appear in the pairwise mutual information
and conditional mutual information that we obtained from
the chain rule:
Colonial Individuality A ∶= I(S
n+1
;S
n
|E
n
)
Organismal Individuality A
∶= I(S
n+1
;S
n
)
Environmental Determined Individuality
nC ∶= I(S
n+1
;E
n
|
S
n
)
(1)
I(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)=SI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)

shared
+ CI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)

complementary
+ UI(S
n+1
;S
n
E
n
)

unique (S
n
wrt E
n
)
+ UI(S
n+1
;E
n
S
n
)

unique (E
n
wrt S
n
)
.
(2)
I(S
n+1
;S
n
)=SI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)+UI(S
n+1
;S
n
E
n
),
(3)
I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)=CI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)+UI(S
n+1
;E
n
S
n
),
(4)
I(S
n+1
;E
n
)=SI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)+UI(S
n+1
;E
n
S
n
),
(5)
I(S
n+1
;S
n
|E
n
)=CI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)+UI(S
n+1
;S
n
E
n
),
In our context the four terms have the following meaning:
a The unique information from the system
UI(S
n+1
;S
n
E
n
)
. This is information maintained by the
system.
b The shared information between the system and environ-
ment
SI(S
n+1
, S
n
, E
n
)
.
c The unique information from the environment
UI(S
n+1
;E
n
S
n
)
. This quantifies the influence of the
environment on the system. (Information flow in the
narrow sense).
d The complementary or synergistic information. Informa-
tion that is only present in the interaction of systems and
environment.
It is important to emphasize that these decompositions
are a means of supporting our formal intuition and do not
correspond to a specification of the information-theoretic
quantities. This choice remains disputed and several alterna-
tive proposals have been published. These are reviewed in
a special issue of the journal Entropy (Lizier etal. 2018).
Nevertheless, the measures that we derive fully accord with
the conceptual decomposition.
Forms ofindividuality
With a good understanding of the implications of partial
information decomposition in hand in hand, we can now
rigorously define three forms of individuality and an addi-
tional measure quantifying contribution of each in the case
of hybrid types. These measures are defined in terms of
the information that is shared by system and environment
(e.g., adaptive information), information that is unique
to either the system or the environment (e.g., memory in
each), and information that depends in some complicated
way on both the system and the environment (e.g., regula-
tory information).
Organismal Individuality
A
Organisms are well adapted when they share through
adaptation or learning significant information with the
environment in which they live. In addition, they contain
a large amount of private information required for effec-
tive function. By maximizing this measure, we are able to
identify complex organisms in their environments.
Colonial Individuality A
Many organisms such as microbes share only a small
amount of information with the environment in which
A
= SI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)+UI(S
n+1
;S
n
E
n
)
A = CI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)+UI(S
n+1
;S
n
E
n
)
1
The terms of the partial information decomposition in Williams and
Beer (2010) were derived from a set of very general axioms. These
axioms, however, do not define concrete measures for the specific
term. One needs an additional definition for one of the four terms.
The original proposal by Williams and Beer (2010) was criticized as
counterintuitive and several other proposals have been made, such as
(Harder etal. 2013; Bertschinger etal. 2014; Finn and Lizier 2018;
James etal. 2017), albeit no consensus has yet been reached. In this
paper, we will use the decomposition as a conceptual framework to
interpret classical information-theoretic quantities.
216 Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
they live. They contain regulatory mechanisms that allow
for adaptation through ongoing interaction between their
biotic and abiotic environment. By maximizing this meas-
ure, we are able to identify “environmentally regulated
aggregations,” which we call “colonial individuals.
Environmental determination nC
This measure quantifies the degree of environmental
determinism on the temporal evolution of an individual.
When this measure is minimized an individual becomes
completely insensitive to the environment—and hence is
neither in the organismal or colonial form—and not in
any real sense adaptive. It represents the persistence of an
environmental memory capable through interaction with
the system of generating structure, such as temperature
gradients in a fluid that produce vortices.
Environmental Coding
The intuition behind this measure is to quantify the dif-
ference between a colonial and organismal measure of
individuality. The difference is captured by the difference
between shared information (e.g., adaptive information)
and the interaction of individual and environment (e.g.,
regulatory information). One way to think about this is
how much information can be encoded about the envi-
ronment in the system innately (e.g., inherited informa-
tion) versus how much information needs to be encoded
through ongoing interaction. When the measure is large
nature dominates nurture. As the measure declines, nur-
ture begins to dominate nature.
Individuality measures inanillustrative example
To gain a better understanding of each of these measures, we
work through a quantitative example.
We consider two binary units
E
n
and
S
n
, with state sets
{−1, +1}
. Following the general structure introduced in
sect.2.1 and Fig.1, these states are synchronously updated
according to the following conditional distribution:
where
nC = I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)=CI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)
+
UI
(
S
n+1
;
E
n
S
n
)
NTIC = SI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)−CI(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)
p(s
n+1
, e
n+1
|s
n
, e
n
)=p
S
(s
n+1
|s
n
, e
n
)
p
E
(e
n+1
|s
n
, e
n
),
(6)
p
S
(s
n+1
|
s
n
, e
n
)=
1
1 + e
2s
n+1
(
𝛿
S
+𝛼
S
s
n
+𝛽
S
e
n
+𝛾
S
s
n
e
n
)
(7)
p
E
(e
n+1
|
s
n
, e
n
)=
1
1 + e
2e
n+1
(
𝛿
E
+𝛼
E
e
n
+𝛽
E
s
n
+𝛾
E
s
n
e
n
)
.
Evaluating the individual conditional distributions, we
obtain
and correspondingly
Finally, this yields the following stochastic matrix with
entries
p(s
n+1
, e
n+1
|s
n
, e
n
)
:
We apply each individuality measure to this stochastic
process. The results of this analysis are shown in Fig.2 for
a random environment and in Fig.3 for an environment with
memory. The panel sweeps through three coupling param-
eters for the systems state
s
n+1
:
𝛼
S
—the coupling parameter
of the system state to its previous state
s
n
,
𝛽
S
—the coupling
parameter to the environment, and
𝛾
S
the coupling parameter
mediating the combined influence of the previous system
and environmental states. When
𝛾
S
= 0
, we are not imposing
any higher-order correlations on the time series.
When the value of
𝛾
S
= 0
, we detect colonial indi-
viduals as well as organismal individuals most readily at
high values of
𝛼
S
and
𝛽
S
. When there are no higher-order
interactions between system and environment then these
two types of individual become indistinguishable in this
parameter region and represent unique information in the
system state. Both forms of individuality become more
visible as more information is transmitted into the future.
In the case of a non-random environment, the system can
adapt to the environment and we observe high values of
A
together with low values of A and nC for high values
p
S
(+1| + 1, +1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
S
+𝛼
S
+𝛽
S
+𝛾
S
)
=∶ a
S
p
S
(+1| 1, +1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
S
𝛼
S
+𝛽
S
𝛾
S
)
=∶ b
S
p
S
(+1| + 1, 1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
S
+𝛼
S
𝛽
S
𝛾
S
)
=∶ c
S
p
S
(+1
|
1, 1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
S
𝛼
S
𝛽
S
+𝛾
S
)
=∶ d
S
p
E
(+1| + 1, +1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
E
+𝛼
E
+𝛽
E
+𝛾
E
)
=∶ a
E
p
E
(+1| 1, +1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
E
+𝛼
E
𝛽
E
𝛾
E
)
=∶ b
E
p
E
(+1| + 1, 1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
E
𝛼
E
+𝛽
E
𝛾
E
)
=∶ c
E
p
E
(+1
|
1, 1)=
1
1 + e
2
(
𝛿
E
𝛼
E
𝛽
E
+𝛾
E
)
=∶ d
E
(+1, +1) (−1, +1) (+1, 1) (−1, 1)
(+1, +1) a
S
a
E
(1 a
S
)a
E
a
S
(1 a
E
) (1 a
S
)(1 a
E
)
(−1, +1) b
S
b
E
(1 b
S
)b
E
b
S
(1 b
E
) (1 b
S
)(1 b
E
)
(+1, 1) c
S
c
E
(1 c
S
)c
E
c
S
(1 c
E
) (1 c
S
)(1 c
E
)
(−1, 1) d
S
d
E
(1 d
S
)d
E
d
S
(1 d
E
) (1 d
S
)(1 d
E
)
217Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
of
|𝛽
S
|
and low values of
𝛾
S
. Thus, the information flow
from the environment into the system represented by high
values of nC in the case of the random environment gets
now internalized into the system.
As the value of
𝛾
S
increases, the signatures of the organ-
ismal and colonial individuals diverge. Colonial individuals
are most apparent at low values of
𝛼
S
and
𝛽
S
where most of
the information persistence derives from ongoing interac-
tions between system and environment. Organismal indi-
viduals begin to disappear at high
𝛾
as autonomy is lost. It is
preserved only at high levels of
𝛼
.
The environmentally determined information transforms
into colonial individuality at low
𝛾
to becoming almost indis-
tinguishable from it at high values of
𝛾
S
. This is because
when the system and environment become strongly coupled,
complementary information comes to dominate the signal,
and the environment on its own becomes less predictive of
the future state of the system.
The effect of
𝛾
S
is to reduce the total entropy of the system
(by creating systematic correlations and hence regularities
in the information channel), and to reverse the pattern of
total mutual information between successive time steps. This
Fig. 2 Mutual information between two time steps (Total_MI),
Entropy of the system (H_sys), colonial (A) and organismal (A_star)
individuality, and environmental determination (nC) for different val-
ues of
𝛼
S
,
𝛽
S
, and for
𝛾
S
(subscript “S” omitted in the figure) with a
random environment
𝛼
E
=
𝛽
E
=
𝛾
E
=
0
218 Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
value is a minimum for low
𝛼
S
and
𝛽
S
when
𝛾
S
= 0
and a
maximum when
𝛾
S
= 5.
From the previous empirical example, we discern a pro-
cess for identifying different forms of informational individ-
uals in a more general setting. We find that system–environ-
ment distinctions increase in those parameters that increase
independent memory (
𝛼, 𝛽
) when higher-order coupling is
low. When this coupling increases, organismal individuals
disappear and colonial individuals appear with reduced inde-
pendent memories.
Let as assume that the transition parameters are held
constant and we vary the system states. By systematically
increasing the number of variables that we assign to the
target system while reducing the environmental states, we
can deduce whether this procedure leads to an increase in
a suitable individuality measure.
If the expansion of the boundary of the system does not
lead to an increase in information, then we have incorpo-
rated an environmental variable needlessly. In this way,
individuals maximize their prediction of the future while
minimizing their coding capacity. If individuality increases
as we expand our system and environmental determination
decreases, then we have grounds for the belief that we are
Fig. 3 Mutual information between two time steps (Total_MI), Entropy of the system (H_sys), colonial (A) and organismal (A_star) individual-
ity, and environmental determination (nC) for different values of
𝛼
S
,
𝛽
S
, and for
𝛾
S
with a correlated environment
𝛼
E
=
2 𝛽
E
=
𝛾
E
=
0
219Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
capturing more of the individual by including more pro-
cesses formerly treated as environmental.
Let us denote the original system with S and the part of
the initial environment which becomes the system by
ΔS
.
The remaining environment should be denoted by
E
.
Environmental determination
We get the two information flows
and
Using some algebra we get
The first term subtracts the information flow which
is now internalized and the second term adds the flow
which resided previously in the environment. Clearly the
system becomes more closed if the former, now internal-
ized flow, is larger than the latter.
Organismal individuality
Let us start with the simpler measure
A
, the mutual
information between subsequent states:
and
Colonial individuality
Both individuality measures can only grow or stay constant
with increasing system size when information is available
but they never decrease. Thus, they are not sufficient to
detect the precise boundaries between individuals. In order
to obtain precise boundaries we would need to impose a
cost function—or regularizer—on system size to establish
a threshold for termination. Our objectives here are not to
find the optimal partition but present different informational
“windows” on individuality.
nC = I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)
= I(S
n+1
;E
n
ΔS
|
S
n
)
nC
= I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;E
n
|
ΔS
n
, S
n
)
nC
= nC I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n
)
+ IS
n+1
;E
n
|
ΔS
n
, S
n+1
, S
n
)
A
= I(S
n+1
;S
n
)
A
�∗
= I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;S
n
ΔS
n
)
= A
+ IS
n+1
;S
n
|S
n+1
)+I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n
).
A = I(S
n+1
;S
n
|E
n
)
= I(S
n+1
;S
n
|E
n
ΔS
n
)
A
= I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;S
n
ΔS
n
|E
n
)
= A + I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;ΔS
n
|E
n
)
+ IS
n+1
;S
n
|E
n
ΔS
n
S
n+1
)
= A + I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|
E
n
)+IS
n+1
;S
n
ΔS
n
|
E
n
S
n+1
)
Implications ofITI
Fundamental units andmechanism
Using an information-theoretic framework (ITI) applied to a
stochastic process, we derived a number of principled quan-
tities that capture forms and degrees of individuality. The
approach has been somewhat formal as we have sought to pro-
vide a means for “detecting” or “perceiving” through an appro-
priate information-theoretic filter individuals in a variety of
different evolutionary and ecological contexts. This is related
to research that seeks to discover integrated spatiotemporal
patterns for the purpose of discovering “agents” in a stochastic
process (Biehl etal. 2016). It is also worth noting that the idea
we can detect fundamental units in adaptive systems using
an appropriate filter provides a second conceptual connection
to physics beyond the thermodynamic connection outlined in
A way forward section and discussed again in the next para-
graph. Despite good theoretical reasons to expect the existence
of particles beyond those predicted by the Standard Model,
there is no direct empirical evidence BSM particles exist. To
search for such particles, physicists are moving toward “model
free” approaches, enhanced by machine learning (Collins etal.
2018), that allow detection of subtle correlations or anomalies
in the data without making assumptions a priori about how
the particles (presumably producing the anomalies) behave.
Questions of individuality connect to challenges related to
explaining how functional space and time scales consolidate
and new function emerges in biological systems (reviewed in
Flack 2012, 2017a, b). This work suggests one driver of new
function is the reduction in environmental uncertainty through
the construction of dynamical processes with a range of char-
acteristic time constants, described as nested slow variables.
Slow variables are coarse-grained encodings of fast, micro-
scopic dynamics. Slow variables provide better predictors
of the local future configuration of a system than the states
of the fluctuating microscopic components. As proposed in
Flack (2017b) maximizing uncertainty reduction through the
computation of nested, coarse-grained slow variables, should
be an organizing principle of adaptive systems . This begs the
question of how computations supporting regularity estima-
tion get refined through learning and evolutionary dynamics
and whether information processing is ever optimal, as some
studies intriguingly suggest (Tkacik etal. 2012), and which
provide support for the use of the information-theoretic for-
malisms supporting our individuality lenses.
Levels ofselection
The purpose of this paper has been to place the discussion
of adaptive individuality on a solid logical and probabilistic
foundation. In order to do so, we have taken a fair amount
220 Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
for granted, including the ability to make accurate measure-
ments at arbitrary scales of granularity and over scales of
time that are historically meaningful. We have also neglected
to discuss those mechanisms that make heredity or transmis-
sion possible in the first place, in other words, robustness
mechanisms that enable the error-free, or low error, trans-
mission of information across generations. We have avoided
discussing the specifics of the functional or selective benefits
of hierarchical levels, concentrating on their identification.
It is fair to assume that long-lived aggregates could develop
the capacity to replicate and become a significant target
for selection and hence a bona fide level at which selection
operates, which for some is what is implied by biological
individuality (Okasha 2006), in which case our approach
could provide a means of identifying both pre-individuals
(low autonomy) as well as fully fledged individuals (high
autonomy). We discuss each of these topics in more detail
below.
a The partitioning requirement In the previous discussion,
we have “defined” the quantities, autonomy, closure and
sufficiency, in terms of system and environment, but we
have not provided any mechanisms that might gener-
ate a time series with appropriate values, or discussed
how we might go about identifying the best system and
environmental variables in the first place. Moreover, the
choice of time scale will be instrumentally critical, as
over very short or very long time scales we are unlikely
to observe the regularities from which we seek to derive
the individuality quantities: autonomy, sufficiency, and
closure. It is our belief that few of these attributes (sys-
tem and environment variables, time scales, etc) can be
known in advance, and that it is precisely through the
algorithmic determination of the individual that each
will obtain relative support.
b The robustness requirement Further to identifying nested
or hierarchical partitions, we also require some specifi-
cation of the machine itself—the generator of the time
series. This will be equated with parts of the individual
and needs to possess some level of robustness or an
error-correcting property. This is because individuality
in adaptive systems often seems to be associated with
adaptive mechanisms of homeostasis—mechanisms that
monitor internal states and ensure that deviations are
minimized. It is this self-preserving quality of the indi-
vidual that allows us to make some useful discrimina-
tion between physical phenomena and biological ones,
without exaggerating the dynamical differences.
c The levels of selection In many previous treatments of
individuality, the idea that the individual has a special
evolutionary status has been posited. This is presented in
terms of levels of selection, where coarse-grained aggre-
gates achieve a coordinated persistence property that
now allows them to be treated as segregating, selective
units. The most popular formalism for thinking about
this process is presented in terms of the Price equation,
which describes how the mean value of a trait changes
as a function of the covariance in that trait and fitness,
and the previous value of the trait. Of interest to us here
is that the Price equation assumes some partition of trait
values into groups and attempts to do this in such a way
as to best capture the evolution of the mean value of the
trait in the population. Assuming some true underlying
structure and dynamics (see appendix of Nowak etal.
2010), the accuracy of the equation will depend on the
choice of partition (Krakauer and Flack 2010b), and the
ITI could provide such a principled platform for mod-
eling.
Future work
Related formalisms
Before closing with a brief discussion of algorithms, a
few comments about adjacent mathematical measures
and approaches. Our approach is related to the concept of
autopoiesis developed by Maturana (Maturana 1975) who
emphasizes the “unity” of a network of processes engaged
in self-production in terms of autonomy (Maturana 1980),
and the idea of a Gestalt perception in which the figure is
observed to be more than the sum of its parts and distinct
from the parts of its grounding.
Another related body of work is the study of modularity
network sciences. For static structures, there are reasonable
definitions of modularity. Many of these definitions are asso-
ciated with procedures for partitioning microscopic data into
tightly bound groups, such as communities. For example, in
networks quantitative modularity measures seek partitions
of nodes and edges into sets that are statistically overrepre-
sented in data when compared to an appropriate null model
(Newman 2016). Developmental definitions of modularity,
such as those applied to limb formation, or the appearance
of body segments, also provide a window into individuality
(Davidson etal. 2004) but they have not been presented in
the form of quantitative measures for identification as they
have in network science.
There is also a connection to the free-energy principle
(FEP) as developed by Karl Friston and collegues Ram-
stead etal. (2018). Like the ITI, the FEP is built from first
principles, moving forward from Schrodinger, and with the
goal of explaining how adaptive systems resist decay and
221Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
persist over time. It also stresses uncertainty reduction, but
does through the lens of minimizing free energy. The FEP
rests on the idea that adaptive systems will occupy a small
bounded set of states within the total possible phase space.
Furthermore, adaptive systems accomplish free energy mini-
mization through construction of partitions that separate the
organisms from its environment—in the FEP formulation
this “filter” is a Markov blanket, which specify the condi-
tional independence of internal and external states, with the
internal states only perceiving the external states through
the Markov filter.
Algorithmic implementation
The last topic we discuss briefly is implementation of our
measure on data. The ITI is mathematical formalism based
on first principles for capturing information flow from the
past to the future and which allows us to rigorously define
a number of different forms of individuality. We have not
provided an optimal algorithm for individuality-induction
which we have left this for future work. Here, we do, how-
ever, note a few requirements.
A key empirical requirement is the careful measurement
of a number of hypothesized individual attributes or proper-
ties over the course of time. For example, the abundance of
organisms in a population; the genetic or phenotypic states
of cells or tissues over time, the firing rates of neurons over
time. In each case, we require a consistent time series of
measurements in an appropriate coordinate frame (concen-
tration, spatial position, firing rate, chemical concentration)
that provide the input to our algorithms. It is our contention
that many existing biological concepts (e.g., tightly coor-
dinated replicators, developmental individuals), will be
identified and become perceptible through this procedure.
Many novel “individuals” might also be identified, includ-
ing those at the societal level that are currently deprecated
as derivative or epiphenomenal of lower level forms. And of
great interest preadaptive organizations that emerge quickly
relative to their own dynamical history and that experience
a relatively long environmental history (i.e., self-organizing
structures such as vortices that are picked up by the environ-
mental determination measure).
Acknowledgements We thank Lynn Nyhart and Scott Lidgard for their
motivating questions, guidance and careful thoughts on this topic. We
thank Cormac McCarthy for his close reading and recommendations.
JCF and DCK were supported by the U.S. Army Research Office MURI
award under contract number W911NF-13-1-0340 and John Templeton
Foundation (JTF) through The Principles of Complexity award to the
Santa Fe Institute. JCF was supported by JTF through St. Andrew’s
grant 13337. JCF was also supported by the Bengier Foundation and
the Proteus Foundation.
Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons
Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing,
adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format,
as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the
source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate
if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this
article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless
indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not
included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended
use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted
use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright
holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creat iveco mmons
.org/licen ses/by/4.0/.
Appendix: Reections onclosure
andsuciency
We can think about an individual as a system that is a
sufficient predictor of its own future. This implies that
that
S
n1
does not add any information about
S
n+1
besides
the one already contained in
S
n
. Formally this reads as
I(S
n+
;S
n1
|S
n
)=0
.
Note that by the Markovian structure of the system–envi-
ronment interaction
Thus,
I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)=I(S
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
)+I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n1
, S
n
)
which means that informational closure implies sufficiency,
i.e.,
Informational closure is therefore a stronger notion than suf-
ficiency
2
which allows the system to be influenced by the
environment as long as this influence cannot be predicted
from within the system.
Considering longer histories
The above calculations can be generalized to longer
histories:
I(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)=I(S
n+1
;S
n1
, S
n
, E
n
)
= I(S
n+1
;S
n
)+[I(S
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
)
+ I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n1
, S
n
)]
= I(S
n+1
;S
n
)+I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)
nC = I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
)=0
I(S
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
)=0
I(S
n+1
;S
n
, E
n
)=I(S
n+1
;S
n
nl
, E
n
nk
)
= I(S
n+1
;E
n
nk
)+I(S
n+1
;S
n
nl
|E
n
nk
)
= I(S
n+1
;S
n
nl
)+I(S
n+1
;E
n
nk
|S
n
nl
)
= I(S
n+1
;S
n
nl
)+[I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
nl
)
+ I(S
n+1
;E
n1
nk
|S
n
nl
, E
n
)

=0
]
2
For a more general setting this was shown in (Pfante etal. 2014).
222 Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
Thus, overall the same relationships between autonomy, clo-
sure and sufficiency are obtained
Suciency expansion andboundary detection
We can explore sufficiency a little more formally in terms of
Markov conditions. We consider a system as self-sufficient
if its dynamics are Markovian, i.e.,
In the following we consider only the case
m = 1
:
We get for the non-sufficiency
nS
= I(S
n+1
;S
n1
|
S
n
)
of
the enlarged system
Now we apply the chain rule:
which leads to
We see that the only term which can lead to a decrease in
the non-sufficiency is
I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n
)−I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n1
S
n
)
.
I(S
n+1
;E
n
nk
)+I(S
n+1
;S
n
|E
n
nk
)

A
k
= I(S
n+1
;S
n
)
  
A
+ I(S
n+1
;S
n1
nl
|S
n
)

(non-)sufficiency
+I(S
n+1
;E
n
|S
n
nl
)
= A
+ nC
I(S
n+1
;S
nm
|S
n1
, , S
nm+1
)=0.
(8)
I
(S
n+1
;S
n1
|
S
n
)=I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;S
n1
ΔS
n1
|
S
n
ΔS
n
)
I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;S
n1
ΔS
n1
|S
n
ΔS
n
)
= I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
ΔS
n
)
+ I(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;ΔS
n1
|S
n1
, S
n
ΔS
n
)
I
(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
ΔS
n
)
= I(S
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
ΔS
n
)+IS
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
ΔS
n
S
n+1
)
I
(S
n+1
ΔS
n+1
;ΔS
n1
|S
n1
, S
n
ΔS
n
)
= I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n1
|S
n1
, S
n
ΔS
n
)
+ IS
n+1
;ΔS
n1
|S
n1
S
n
ΔS
n
S
n+1
)
and
I
(S
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
ΔS
n
)
= I(S
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
)+I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n1
S
n
)
I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n
)
nS
=
nS
I
(
S
n+1
;
Δ
S
n
|S
n
)+
I
(
S
n+1
;
Δ
S
n
|S
n1
S
n
)
+ I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n1
|S
n1
, S
n
ΔS
n
)
+ IS
n+1
;ΔS
n1
|S
n1
S
n
ΔS
n
S
n+1
)
+ IS
n+1
;S
n1
|S
n
ΔS
n
S
n+1
)
nS
= nS −[I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n
)−I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n
|S
n1
S
n
)]
+ I(S
n+1
;ΔS
n1
|
S
n+1
S
n
)+IS
n+1
;S
n1
|
S
n
S
n+1
)
It can be interpreted as the internalized information from
S
n1
to
S
n+1
.
The other two terms are always positive and related to
new information flows through the environment—which are
made possible by enlarging the system and which are not
accounted for by nS.
References
Anderson PW (1972) More is different. Science 177:393–396
Andreu-Moreno I, Sanjuán R (2018, 2019/04/06). Collective infection
of cells by viral aggregates promotes early viral proliferation and
reveals a cellular-level allee effect. Curr Biol 28(20):3212–3219.
e4
Bertschinger N, Olbrich E, Ay N, Jost J (2008) Autonomy: an informa-
tion theoretic perspective. Biosystems 91(2):331–345
Bertschinger N, J Rauh, E Olbrich, J Jost (2013) Shared informa-
tion—new insights and problems in decomposing information in
complex systems. In: Gilbert T, Kirkilionis M, Nicolis G (eds)
Proceedings of the European Conference on Complex Systems
2012, Springer Proceedings in Complexity. Springer, pp 251–269
Bertschinger N, Rauh J, Olbrich E, Jost J, Ay N (2014) Quantifying
unique information. Entropy 16(4):2161–2183
Biehl M, Ikegami T, Polani D (2016) Towards information based spa-
tiotemporal patterns as a foundation for agent representation in
dynamical systems. arXiv :1605.05676 v1
Buss L (1987) The evolution of individuality. Princeton University
Press, Princeton
Callcott B, Sterelny K (2011) The major transitions in evolution revis-
ited. MIT Press, Cambridge
Clarke E (2011) The problem of biological individuality. Biol Theory
5:312–325
Collins J, Howe K, Nachman B (2018) Anomaly detection for
resonant new physics with machine learning. Phys Rev Lett
121(24):241803. https ://doi.org/10.1103/PhysR e vLe t t.121.24180 3
Cover T, Thomas J (1991) Elements of information theory. Wiley, New
York
Daniels BC, Ellison CJ, Krakauer DC, Flack JC (2016) Quantifying
collectivity. Curr Opin Neurobiol 37:106–113 Neurobiology of
cognitive behavior
Davidson B, Jacobs MW, Swalla BJ (2004) The individual as a module:
solitary-to colonial transitions in Metazoan evolution and develop-
ment. In: Schlosser G, Wagner GP (eds) Modularity in develop-
ment and evolution. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago,
pp 443–465 Chapter20
Dawkins R (1983) The extended phenotype. Oxford University Press,
New York
Defranceschi M, Le Bris C (2000) Mathematical models and methods
for abinitio quantum chemistry. Springer, Berlin
Dupré J (2009) It Is Not Possible to Reduce Biological Explanations
to Explanations in Chemistry and/or Physics. In: Contemporary
debates in philosophy of biology. Wiley-Blackwell, pp 32–47
Esser K, Lemke PA, Hock B (2001) Fungal associations. Springer,
Berlin
Finn C, Lizier JT (2018) Pointwise partial information decomposition
using the specificity and ambiguity lattices. Entropy 20(4):297
Flack J (2017a) Lifes information hierarchy. Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, pp 283–302
Flack JC (2012) Multiple time-scales and the developmental
dynamics of social systems. Philos Trans R Soc B: Biol Sci
367(1597):1802–1810
223Theory in Biosciences (2020) 139:209–223
1 3
Flack JC (2017b) Coarse-graining as a downward causation mechanism.
Philos Trans R Soc A: Math Phys Eng Sci 375(2109):20160338
Gell-Mann M (1995) The quark and the jaguar: adventures in the sim-
ple and the complex. St. Martin’s Griffin, New York
Gilbert SF, Sapp J, Tauber AI (2012) A symbiotic view of life: we have
never been individuals. Q Rev Biol 87:1–7
Gow NAR, Robson GD, Gadd GM, Gadd GM (2008) The fungal col-
ony. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Harder M, Salge C, Polani D (2013) Bivariate measure of redundant
information. Phys Rev E 87:012130
Hughes RN (1990) Functional biology of clonal animals. Springer,
Berlin
James RG, Emenheiser J, Crutchfield JP (2017) Unique information
via dependency constraints. arXiv :1709.06653
Keller EF (2009) It Is possible to reduce biological explanations to
explanations in chemistry and/or physics. In: Ayala FJ, Arp R
(eds) Contemporary debates in philosophy of biology. Wiley-
Blackwell, Hoboken, pp 19–31 Chapter1
Krakauer DC, Flack JC (2010a) Better living through physics. Nature
467:661
Krakauer DC, Flack JC (2010b) Better living through physics. Nature
467:661
Krakauer DC, Zanotto P (2006) Viral individuality and limitations of
the life concept. MIT Press, Cambridge Chapter23
Laughlin RB, Pines D (2000) The theory of everything. Proc Natl Acad
Sci 97(1):28–31
Lizier J, Bertschinger N, Jost J, Wibral M (2018) Informative decompo-
sition of target effects from multi-source interactions: perspectives
on previous current and future work. Entropy 20(4):307
Maturana HR (1975) The organization of the living: a theory of the
living organization. Int J Man–Machine Stud 7(3):313–332
Maturana HR (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the
living. Springer, Berlin
Müller I (2007) A history of thermodynamics: the doctrine of energy
and entropy. Springer, Berlin
Newman MEJ (2016) Equivalence between modularity optimization
and maximum likelihood methods for community detection. Phys
Rev E 94:052315
Nowak MA, Tarnita CE, Wilson EO (2010) The evolution of eusocial-
ity. Nature 466:1057
Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford Univer-
sity Press, Oxford
Pfante O, Olbrich E, Bertschinger N, Ay N, Jost J (2014) Comparison
between different methods of level identification. Adv Complex
Syst 17(02):1450007
Pradeu T (2012) The limits of the self: immunology and biological
identity. Oxford University Press, Oxford
Ramstead MJD, Badcock PB, Friston KJ (2018) Answering schröding-
er’s question: a free-energy formulation. Phys Life Rev 24:1–16
Rasmussen S, Chen L, Deamer D, Krakauer DC, Packard NH, Stadler
PF, Bedau MA (2004) Transitions from nonliving to living matter.
Science 303(5660):963–965
Rescher N (2007) The promise of process philosophy. In: Boundas CV
(ed) The edinburgh companion to twentieth-century philosophies.
Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, pp 143–155 Chapter8
Rieppel O (2013) Biological individuals and natural kinds. Biol Theory
7(2):162–169
Santelices B (1999) How many kinds of individual are there? Trends
Ecol Evol 14(4):152–155
Schrodinger E (2012) What is life?. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge
Szathmáry E, Smith JM (1997) From replicators to reproducers: the
first major transitions leading to life. J Theor Biol 187(4):555–571
Tkacik G, Walczak AM, Bialek W (2012) Optimizing information flow
in small genetic networks. iii. a self-interacting gene. Phys Rev E
Stat Nonlinear Soft Matter Phys 85:041903
Weinberg S (1995) Reductionism redux. The New York Review of
Books
Williams PL, Beer RD (2010) Nonnegative decomposition of multi-
variate information. arXiv :1004.2515
Wilson RA, Barker M (2013) The Biological Notion of an individual.
In: Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Metaphysics Research
Lab, Stanford University
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to
jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Discussion

These points outline the main theories of individuality exposited in this paper: individuality can be continuous, it can emerge at any level of organization, and it can be nested. "In an ideal case, visitors to an exoplanet would have a procedure for identifying or “perceiving” individuals based on a quantitative survey with minimal prior knowledge of the type of life form that they expect to encounter. In the next sections of the paper, we briefly review a few key standard assumptions about individuality in biology and challenges to formalizing the concept. We then discuss a way forward and develop an information-theoretic formalism." The key question of this paper: "The question we seek to address is more limited. How do we identify individuals without relying on features like cell membranes that may be solutions to challenges faced by particular systems for maintaining integrity rather than foun- dational properties? We want to allow for the possibility that microbes and loosely bound ecological assemblages such as microbial mats and cultural and technological systems, when viewed with a mathematical lens, qualify as individuals even though their boundaries are more fluid than the organisms we typically allow." Here is a great background article on this topic, with quotes from several of the authors from this paper: https://www.quantamagazine.org/what-is-an-individual-biology-seeks-clues-in-information-theory-20200716/ Information theory, as its name suggests, is the study of information. The theory was originally formulated to explain the fundamental limits on signal processing and communication operations (i.e. data compression), and was proposed by Claude Shannon in 1948 in "A Mathematical Theory of Communication". More background: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Information_theory Nature of life is process-driven. Recall Alfred North Whitehead's process philosophy and Buckminster Fullerene's: "I Seem to be a Verb". Many of the authors from this paper work at the Santa Fe institute. Founded in 1984, the Santa Fe institute is an independent, nonprofit theoretical research institute where the research focuses on complex adaptive systems, applied to different fields (biology, social systems, computational sciences...etc). They produce several courses on complexity/chaos theory, including different applications, that are worth exploring: https://www.santafe.edu/engage/learn/courses More on the SFI: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Santa_Fe_Institute Even though the existence of DNA had been known since 1869, its role in reproduction and its helical shape were still unknown at the time of Schrödinger's lecture and his idea stimulated scientists to search for the genetic molecule in the 1950s: "The mere fact that we speak of hereditary properties indicates that we recognize the permanence to be of the almost absolute. For we must not forget that what is passed on by the parent to the child is not just this or that peculiarity...Such features we may conveniently select for studying the laws of heredity. But actually it is the whole (four- dimensional) pattern of the phenotype, all the visible and manifest nature of the individual, which is reproduced without appreciable change for generations, permanent within centuries—though not within tens of thousands of years—and borne at each transmission by the material in a structure of the nuclei of the two cells which unite to form the fertilized egg cell. That is a marvel." This paper similarly takes a Schrödinger-esque leap in their theoretical speculation about the fundamental units of biology. Unfortunately, biology is a field that is under-theorized and relatively over-quantified. "In Schrödinger’s case, the physical feature of greatest importance to biology was the long-lived covalent bond. But for many reasons this line of approach has failed to deliver the deep and unifying insights based on physics (Anderson 1972), from which powerful biological ideas—such as adaptation or individuality—might be derived." This is the famous Entropy formula from Claude Shannon's work on information theory. For a deeper dive into the formula: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Entropy_(information_theory) "What Is Life? The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell" by the Nobel Prize-winning physicist Erwin Schrödinger, is based on a course of public lectures that Schrödinger gave in February 1943 to an audience of about 400. Schrödinger's lecture focuses on one important question: "how can the events in space and time which take place within the spatial boundary of a living organism be accounted for by physics and chemistry?" Here is an annotated version "What is life?": https://fermatslibrary.com/s/what-is-life